Copyright © 2016
Avello Publishing Journal
ISSN: 2049 - 498X
Issue 1 Volume 6:
A Synthesis of
‘Analytic’ and ‘Continental’ Philosophy.
Carlos Rodríguez Sutil, University
of Complutense, Madrid, Spain.
Relational
psychoanalysis and other postmodern psychoanalytical orientations manifest their
opposition to Descartes’ ontological dualism and its postulation of an internal
more or less isolated mind. This ontology became long time ago the official
language -the ‘official doctrine’ (Gilbert Ryle). Psychoanalysis understood as
a technique assumes that an isolated mind, the analyst, is doing something to
another isolated mind, the patient, or, at worst, the reverse.
Freud
sometimes managed the conception of an unconscious subject relatively isolated
from his environment, a solipsistic ego under the control of primary narcissism. Fonagy doesn’t maintain, fortunately, such
classical concepts as ‘primary narcissism’ or the drive/instinct theory, but gets
trapped if not on the Cartesian thought at least in some form of the ‘official
doctrine’ language, and his theorization conveyed and image excessively introspective of
the action-reaction dynamic that is established between the infant and its
social environment. The
mind is not born with the individual but develops in the context of human
interaction and the mind is not only internal but also external, mainly
external, that is, the pragmatic context of interpersonal relationships. The internal space is
something that is created (Vygotsky, Wittgenstein).
Before practice had demonstrates that the
letters of the alphabet could bind winged words in row after row of script, no
one would have conceived of a storage room or wax tablet within the mind.
Ivan Illich (1993, pp. 38-39)
Throw away the book. (Leon Hoffman cited by
Paul Fonagy, 1999 b)
Chuang Tzu and Hui Tzu were strolling along the
dam of the Hao River when Chuang Tzu said,
"See how the minnows come out and dart around where they please! That's
what fish really enjoy!"
Hui Tzu said, "You're not a fish - how do
you know what fish enjoy?"
Chuang Tzu said, "You're not I, so how do
you know I don't know what fish enjoy?"
Hui Tzu said, "I'm not you, so I certainly
don't know what you know. On the other hand, you're certainly not a fish ‑ so that still proves you don't know what fish enjoy!"
Chuang Tzu said, "Let's go back to your
original question, please. You asked me how I know what fish enjoy ‑ so you already knew I knew it when you asked the question. I know it by
standing here beside the Hao."
— Zhuangzi, 17, tr. Watson 1968:188-9
This
Taoist tale clearly shows the huge difficulties and contradictions we face when
we tray to theorize about what really happens inside people’s minds. It is a field full of quicksand. Let’s take another perspective on this enigma. We are going to see a
fragment of and old film directed by the great master Alfred Hitchcock “Dial M
for Murder”. Now we read a brief description of the plot.
Tony
Wendice is married to wealthy jetsetter Margot. She had an affair with an
American crime-fiction writer Mark Halliday. Tony discovers the affair and
decides to murder her, both for revenge and to ensure that her money will
continue to finance his comfortable lifestyle. Tony meets an acquaintance from
the University, Swann who has become a small-time criminal. Tony had stolen Margot’s
handbag, which contained a love letter from Mark, and anonymously blackmailed
her. After tricking Swann into leaving his fingerprints on the letter, Tony
offers to pay him to kill Margot; if Swann refuses, Tony will turn him in to
the police as Margot's blackmailer.
The
plan is: the following evening Tony will take Mark to a party, leaving Margot
at home and hiding her latchkey outside the front door of their flat. Swann is
to sneak in when Margot is asleep and hide behind the curtains. At eleven
o'clock, Tony will telephone the flat from the party and Swann must kill Margot
when she answers the phone, open the garden doors, suggesting a burglary gone
wrong, and exit through the front door, hiding the key again. When Margot comes
to the phone, Swann tries to strangle her, but she manages to grab a pair of
scissors and kill him. She picks up the telephone receiver and pleads for help.
When Tony returns to the flat, he calls the police and, before the police
arrive, Tony moves what he thinks is Margot's latchkey from Swann's pocket into
her handbag, plants a Mark's letter on Swann. Chief Inspector Hubbard arrests
Margot after concluding that she killed Swann for blackmailing her. Margot is
found guilty and sentenced to death. On the day before Margot's scheduled
execution, Hubbard asks Tony about large sums of cash he has been spending,
tricks him into revealing that his latchkey is in his raincoat, and discreetly
swaps his own raincoat with Tony's, and as soon as Tony leaves, he uses Tony's
key to re-enter the flat, followed by Mark. Hubbard had already discovered that
the key in Margot's handbag was Swann's latchkey, and deduced that Swann had
put the key back in its hiding place after unlocking the door. Tony retrieves Margot’s
handbag from the police station after discovering that he has no key. The key
from Margot's bag does not work, so he finally uses the hidden key to open the
door, proving his guilt. One of the last scenes shows how Tony ‘internally’
reasoning about the keys and Hubbard offering the audience the voice-off of
what is happening into his head.
Since
the time of Plato (Theaetetus) to think is to speak to oneself but it was not
until Descartes that prevailed the conception of thought as an internal
activity in a closed internal space, the mind (or the brain). One of the most dangerous ideas for a philosopher,
said Wittgenstein (1945-48, § 605, § 606), is that we think in our heads, in a
closed space, hidden. What we see in Hitchcock’s film is real, and in some way
internal, although the signals are all exterior, and show the result of a long developmental
process in a sophisticated intelligent adult, although morally deficient. That
“internal” room is not something given from the scratch.
Relationalists,
intersubjetivists, and other neo-psychoanalysts, as well as Fonagy (2008), in
short, all of us, we manifest our opposition to Descartes ontological dualism
and its postulation of an internal more or less isolated mind. This ontology
became long time ago the official language -the ‘official doctrine’ as Gilbert
Ryle (1945) called it- and today has become a labor of Hercules to get rid of
it. According to this doctrine all human beings, except little children and
idiots, are living two parallel stories: that of the body and that of the mind.
The soul, or mind, is the most immediately knowable existence for each person.
The other's mind is not known directly, although it can be inferred: somehow is
phosphorescent. The place of this inner life, the thought, is the head or, more
specifically, the brain.
One of the erroneous results of this framework is to
consider that all behavior of the person has an internal cause, hidden, in
principle unknown. But the future also,
as Ryle says, is unknown to us, and that does not mean it is hidden anywhere. The
other mistake is to transpose the physical causality to mental events
(Wittgenstein, 1945-49). Official doctrine, therefore, takes as something
given, primitive, the existence of internal mechanisms.
I think that the arguments used by Fonagy
sometimes fall, inadvertently, in current errors due to this Cartesian
perspective.
For instance, Fonagy states his anti-Cartesian position as follows:
Our approach explicitly rejects the classical
Cartesian assumption that mental states are apprehended by introspection; on
the contrary, mental states are discovered
through contingent mirroring interactions with the caregiver. (2008, p. 10; our
emphasize)
Instead I would say,
probably, that ‘mental states’ are not discovered
but created by social interaction. The
expression ‘mental state’ is a cultural-dependent term currently used in
Western societies. There is a more basic principle in Cartesianism than that of
the acquisition of contents by introspections, and it is the ontological
separation of the two substances, mind en matter, spirit and extension,
internal and external.
The
position that we embrace regarding Cartesianism determines to a certain extent
our position in the clinical setting. Psychoanalysis understood as a technique assumes that an isolated mind,
the analyst, is doing something to another isolated mind, the patient, or, at
worst, the reverse. The result can’t be a healthier human being; the human
being is left aside, and the best outcome is a better polished object. Technical
recommendations became fixed rules that persist today in our ‘collective
psychoanalytic superego’ (Orange, Atwood, Stolorow, 1997). We experienced in our relationship with another - coherently with
the technical position- that things
happen sequentially, in the form of action and reaction, as in a one-way
bridge, giving place to a linear causality. In brief, one is agent and the other patient, in
some cases alternatively, in a kind of complementary relationship where the
other's subjectivity is not recognized as such. This action-reaction myth is
the one that dominates the classical psychoanalysis as well as most studies on
current cognitive psychology, indebted to the ‘computer metaphor’. Such point
of view was not shared by pioneers in developmental
psychology, inspired by some form of constructivism, either ‘biological constructivism’
(Piaget and followers), or ‘social constructivism’ (Vygotsky, Bruner).
One
of the main differences between relational and classical psychoanalysis lie in
the increasing proximity or symmetry between therapist and patient, forming
both a therapeutical couple. Therapy is no more something therapist do upon the
patient, but rather a common task of mutuality and reciprocal experience, in a
co-constructed field. Fonagy is well informed about relational psychoanalysis
principles and theories (Cf. Fonagy, 1998). Let us quote Fonagy himself
alluding to relational psychoanalysis:
It would be churlish to
devote too much space to criticizing “work in progress.” These ideas are in the
process of creation and an excessively critical stance can only serve to stifle
such a critical process. I would prefer to point to some areas that I would
like the authors to explore for the sake of completeness. (1998, p. 351)
I
appreciate deeply Fonagy’s theories as really useful instruments in the
clinical work with personality disordered patients. Mentalization theory is
useful as long as it agrees with the Western conception, shared by therapist
and patient, of what is the mind and how goes on. However, for the very same
reason, such a theory, or more precisely certain hard version of it that could
be revealed by a careful reading of Fonagy’s texts, may deserve some criticism.
My intention is, so long as I know, to point to some areas of his thought for
the sake of, not completeness but of a better conceptual framework on Fonagy’s
theoretical stance, and
thus avoid some undesirable potential consequences for clinical work. Well understood,
those are consequences that can occur only in some cases, because fortunately
most clinicians do not follow blindly the theoretical principles they learned,
and are able to ‘throw
away the book’ (Leon Hoffman cited by Paul Fonagy, 1999 a). Kohut (1984) said that empathy was not something he himself had
invented but something already in use by other psychoanalysts of other orientations (Freudians, Kleinians, etc.).
EPISTEMOLOGICAL
CRITIQUE OF MENTALIZATION THEORY
One
of the capabilities that define the human being is to take into account both
his own mental states and that of the others in understanding and predicting
the behavior. In developmental psychology this is what has been called ‘a
theory of mind’ (Cf. Wellman and Liu, 2004). This concept serves to collect all
intuitive ideas each one has about mental functioning and the nature of the
experience, memory, beliefs, attributions, intentions, emotions and desires of
their own and those belonging to other.
However,
when abuses occur by parents, the son’s theory of mind weakens (Fonagy, 1991,
2001; Fonagy y Target, 1996). Fonagy explains convincingly that for the child
is no longer a sure thing to think about desires, because this involves
observing the parent wishes to hurt him. So high representation of mental
events is inhibited, which provides certain benefits for the individual,
allowing him, so to speak, to make a detour against an intolerable mental pain.
The child seeks comfort in a merger down with the object, with a 'parent
rescuer' in fantasy. Therefore it is logical to conclude that the analyst thinking
and talking about thinking of the patient, can help to repair global or focal
defects in the patient's mentalizing ability.
Fonagy
suggest that mentalization is a theory that provides an integrative framework
that could integrate brain and mind and can serve as a ‘common language’ for a
range of therapeutic modalities (Fonagy and Allison, 2014, p.373). The
mentalizing of patients may be a common factor across psychotherapies ‘not
because patients need to learn about the contents of their minds or those of
others, but because mentalizing may be a generic way on increasing epistemic
trust, trust the reality of what the therapist says] and therefore achieving
change in mental function’. (Fonagy and Allison, 2014, p.477)
Taking all this into
account it seems appropriate to seek a precise definition of ‘mentalization’:
We define mentalization
as a form of mostly preconscious imaginative mental activity, namely,
interpreting human behavior in terms of intentional mental states (e.g., needs,
desires, feelings, beliefs, goals, purposes, and reasons). Mentalizing is
imaginative because we have to imagine what other people might be thinking or
feeling; an important indicator of high quality of mentalization is the
awareness that we do not and cannot know absolutely what is in someone else’s
mind. We suggest that a similar kind of imaginative lap is required to
understand one’s one mental experience, particularly in relation to emotionally
charged issues. In order to conceive of
others as having a mind, the individual needs a symbolic representational
system for mental states and also must be able to selectively activate states
of mind in line with particular intentions, which requires attentional control.
(Fonagy, 2008, p. 4, emphasis added).
I beg Fonagy’s pardon if
I compare his stance – complex and comprehensive - in some respects to that of
Andrew Meltzoff. In the mid-70's, Meltzoff discovered that infants between 12
and 21 days of age can imitate both facial and manual gestures (Meltzoff and
Moore, 1977). This behavior implies that human neonates can equate their own
unseen behaviors with gestures they see others perform. More important for what
concerns us here, Meltzoff (2007) proposed the ‘like me’ hypothesis about the
infant development: ‘Here is something that is like me’. The infant experiences
a regular association between his or her own acts and the underlying mental
states. Subsequently, the infant projects internal experiences onto others
performing similar acts, and begins to acquire an understanding of ‘other
minds’: their mental states, emotions, desires, and so on. Imitating is an
innate ability and the comprehension of the other’s mental states is a
derivative. In the same vein Fonagy suggests:
… the ability to give meaning to
psychological experiences evolves as a result of our discovery of the mind
behind other’s actions, which develops
optimally in a relatively safe and secure social context (2008, p. 29, emphasis
added).
I would say not that it “develops” but that it
is “learned” through caregiver’s instructions.
Meltzoff’s
(and Fonagy) hypothesis is indebted for the per
analogiam argument raised by the English philosopher John Stuart Mill, in
the nineteenth century, to solve the ‘other minds’ problem and the risks of
solipsism and isolated mind stemming from Cartesianism. According to this the
statement that other persons also have a consciousness is a conclusion we
derive from their actions and visible manifestations, with the aim of making their
behavior understandable. What is equivalent to say that to attribute consciousness
to others is an inference and not an irrefutable experience.
I
would suggest that the infant doesn’t compare an internal state to a visual
stimulation, but merely that we are ‘programmed’ (is our nature) in a way that
allows us to display spontaneously an emotional response, for instance, in
front of a smile of the caregiver, and so we share his or her ‘mental state’.
The ‘mental state’ is not originally an individual property but it is owned by
at least two people (CF. Knoblauch, 2000, p. 158); the unconscious mind is also
owned by two or more people (Lyons-Ruth, 1999, Gerson, 2004). When we think
steadily that they are indeed private entities, it follows that they are expression
of some inner feelings. Nevertheless, even acknowledging the fact that emotions
require cognitive processing and physiological responses, something that I do not care to recognize, they are social
phenomena that often occur by a perceptual contagion, without any cognitive
mediation.
Fonagy
postulates that symbolic representation of mental states may be seen as a
prerequisite for a sense of identity (Fonagy and Target, 1996; Target and
Fonagy, 1996; Fonagy and Allison, 2014). Thus, patients with severe personality
disorders inhibit their reflective function, and have little access to an accurate picture of their own representational
world. But I suspect that what these patients have is not a hidden or
inhibited representational world, but rather they suffer from a lack, that is,
they show deficits in their representational world. They have not acquired the necessary skills to represent and
therefore don’t have a ‘complete’ representational world.
It
is usual to construct our psychological (cognitive) theories on the basis of
mental representations. However we don’t know yet how representation represents. I feel uncomfortable with
the language of cognitive psychology that pervades relational psychoanalysis,
and even not relational. Perhaps a mentalistic outlook should be suitable for
all patients, regardless of their disorder. Also borderline disordered patients
benefit from a mentalizing attitude on the part of the therapist. I guess these
patients are in greater need of an empathic acceptance and recognition, and
only secondarily to mentalization. Fonagy's answer
probably is that mentalizing is not at all incompatible with acceptance and
recognition, but maybe it should be better to think in terms of relational patterns –
from a descriptive and external point of view - and rhythmicity (a scarcely mentalist concept) in the
relationship therapist-patient.
In
other part Fonagy (Fonagy, 1999 a; Fonagy, Steele, Steele, Leigh, Kennedy,
Mattoon, and Target, 1995) confirms the idea that relationships – the
perception of an analyst having empathy or healing intentions, and not only
interpretations- lead to changes in representational structures. ‘Then, there
is no qualitative difference between the means by which therapeutic change is
achieved via interpretation and via a new relationship’ (Fonagy, 1999 a). To
perceive the therapist as somebody who listens empathetically or has healing
intentions bring changes through the same mechanism of change as
interpretations.
But
these two ‘technical’ stances are not equivalent, because if our praxis is
mainly based on interpretation it means in a concealed way that we have the
truth about the patient’s problems, and consequently adopt the classical
position analyst-patient.
Recently Margy Sperry (2013) based her criticism of
Fonagy's ideas on a similar ground. When Fonagy sees the patient blocked in a
prementalizing stage of development, Sperry says:
Such an assumption
establishes the analyst as an authoritative and objective interpreter of the
meanings and sources of the patient's mentalizing process, and minimizes the
ways that analyst may contribute to the very phenomena that she is explaining.
(id., p. 686).
But Fonagy surely will
answer that:
However, interpretation
is not enforced in some dictatorial way but offered as the start of trying to
make sense of what otherwise may be an apparently meaningless event or feeling.
It becomes a way in which a therapist can demonstrate that they are thinking in
their own mind about the patient’s mind and inevitably it can be given with
varying degrees of competence and sensitivity.
(Bateman and Fonagy, 2004, p. 131)
However, it
is very likely that in a relational analysis we use in a lesser extent the
interpretation than it is usual in classic analysis, and even less in patients
with a borderline functioning.
Fonagy
(2008, pp. 4-9) says that the baby’s experience of himself as having a mind or
self is not a genetic given, but evolves from infancy through childhood and
depends upon the interaction with attuned caregivers. But at the same time he
states that mentalization is the ‘evolutionary pinnacle’ of human intellectual
achievement, after the selection processes of two million years of human
evolution –a proposition that surely Hegel would had endorsed-. It implies a
huge risk of misinterpretation to identify cultural change with Darwinian
evolution. When we refer to the history of humanity prudence advises us to
think merely on a strictly non-evaluative sense, rather than assume the
existence of a positive development, avoiding any idea of improvement and the
culturocentrism. It seems that inspired in social Darwinism, Fonagy suggests
that our exceptional intelligence evolved not to deal with the hostile forces
of nature but rather to deal with competition from other people. This fact is
not grounded on genetics; the ‘social brain’ must reach higher and higher level
of sophistication ‘to stay on top’. I suspect, however, that this
competitiveness is only consistent with Western values.
Mentalizing entails
making sense of the actions of oneself and other’s on the basis of intentional mental states (IIF) (Fonagy, 2008), that is, treating the
object whose behavior you want to predict as a rational or intentional agent
with beliefs and desires. This function provides developmental advantages.
During the second year, children understand that they and others are intentional agents whose actions are
caused by prior states of mind (desires, intentions) and that their actions can
bring about changes in minds as well as bodies (id p. 26). In connection with that you can object that on many occasions desire and
intention don’t precede action but accompany it or, maybe we should say, every
act is an expression of desire or is an intentional action. Maybe Fonagy
conveyed here and image excessively introspective of the action-reaction
dynamic that is established between the infant and its social environment.
Surely it is a much more complex phenomenon: Whose is the desire? When exactly appears
the desire? I have a desire or the desire has caught me? Fonagy’s explanations
sound excessively representational or cognitive. I prefer to talk not of
representations but of patterns of action, mainly procedural.
Let us put
another example. Fonagy added:
In sum, the ability to give meaning
to psychological experiences evolves as a result of our discovery of the mind behind other’s actions, which develops
optimally in a relatively safe and
secure social context. (2008, p. 29, emphasis added).
This fragment
sound quit paradoxical. If I have to seek for a meaning ‘behind’ other’s
actions it is because the social context is not safe and secure at all. What
makes me distrust the good intentions of others is their behavior in the long
run, nothing internal. There might be some signs in the here and now that make
me distrust their ‘intention’. Also ‘intention’ is a generalized term I have
learned to qualify long sequences of behavior. There are a lot of things we
ignore but the truth should not be hidden behind. There is nothing behind, or
‘nothing is hidden’ (Malcolm, 1986).
The
acquisition of mentalization – Fonagy suggests (id., pp. 8-9) - enable the
child to distinguish inner from outer reality and internal mental and emotional
processes from interpersonal events. Regarding that we have to object that
internal events are also interpersonal by definition: Thinking is to speak to
oneself (Platon), and it is impossible for us to feel an emotion that is not
located on the interpersonal level. It is a matter of fact what Fonagy argues:
Self-awareness enables us to modify the way we present ourselves to others and
to mislead them, ‘opens the door to more malicious teasing’ (id., p. 29). Children
under four years usually belief that what they know, everybody knows. Experiments related to the false belief task seem to have probative
value, although some researchers manifested disagreement (Cf. Bloom and German,
2000). Anyway, lying exists, but is an ability we have to learn (Wittgenstein:
Lying is a language-game that needs to be learned like any other one, 1945-49, § 249). And
it is only possible to doubt when there is certainty. We can assert that lying
is only possible when there is truth. That does not mean that all our social
relations are based on deception. For most of our actions you only have to bear
in mind their ‘apparent’ meaning because main part of our social life is based
on confidence.
The French
philosopher and historian of ideas Michel Foucault (1988) introduced the term
‘self-technologies’ which it is possibly applicable
to the theory of mentalization. There are four major types of ‘technologies’:
(I) technologies of production;
(2) technologies of sign systems;
(3) technologies of power, which
determine the conduct of individuals and submit them to certain ends or
domination, an objectivizing of the subject; and
(4) technologies of the self.
Each implies
certain modes of training and modification of individuals, depend on the
historical moment, and not only involve the acquisition of certain skills but
also the acquisition of certain attitudes. Technologies of the self permit
individuals to effect a certain number of operations on their own bodies and
souls, thoughts, conduct, and way of being, so as to transform themselves in
order to attain a certain state of happiness, purity, wisdom, perfection, or
immortality.
The modern
consciousness is devoted to two essential problems which were not present in
the mind of old cultures: Obeying the law and self-knowledge (Foucault, 2001,
p. 305). The two mandates of Greek antiquity were ‘Take care of yourself’ and
‘Know thyself’ and the second covered and obscured the first. Says Bruno Snell
(2007, pp. 289-90) that the bad conscience is a state of mind first reported by
Euripides, as well as shame, embarrassment to others. The Homeric heroes had no
bad conscience, not to say guilt. Instead, they had the Furies or Eumenides,
goddesses of vengeance pursuing those who had committed crimes of blood,
especially parricide. In any case, it was an external factor to the
individual's mind. I would not dare to say that the culture of ancient Greece
was inferior to ours.
On
the one hand, borderline patients sometimes are very sensitive to the other
mental states, well understood in order to control and manipulate (Cf. Fonagy,
1999 b). Mentalizing is an ego or
self-technology developmentally acquired that admits positive and negative
purposes. Fonagy warns us to identify more mentalizing with the best
disposition to serve prosocial ends (2008, p. 29). I would put it in Piagetian
terms: overcoming the stage of concrete operations to reach the stage of formal
operations does not mean it has been reached an autonomous morality. It looks
necessary to complete mentalization theory with a theory of moral development. I
recommend the tripartite scheme of the stages of moral development established
by Lawrence Kohlberg (1964; Kohlberg, Levine, and Hewer, 1984):
pre-conventional, conventional and post-conventional morality. Post-conventional
morality is rather an achievement reached by some individuals, regardless of
their dominant personality, although it is barred for ‘hard skin’ narcissist
and antisocial subjects. In the individual decision-making process three different
expressions arise that represent three groups or types of subjects: ‘I want
it’, ‘the group approves it’, and ‘it is the correct’. The second one,
corresponding to the conventional morality, is characteristic of borderline
personalities, where the ‘internal’ incorporation of the rules has not yet been
achieved; while pre-conventional morality (I want it) is typical of psychopaths
and ‘hard skin’ narcissists. Conventional morality involves the fear of losing
the appreciation of the significant other.
CONCLUSIONS
Freud
sometimes managed the conception of an unconscious subject relatively isolated
from his environment, a solipsistic ego under the control of primary narcissism. Fonagy doesn’t maintain, fortunately, such
classical concepts as ‘primary narcissism’ or the drive/instinct theory, but gets
trapped if not on the Cartesian thought at least in some form of the
"official doctrine" language. For instance when we read: ‘[Small]
Children do not know fully that they are
separate, that their internal world is something private and individual, of
which they will eventually take ownership or at least claim privileged access.’
(Fonagy, 2008, id. p. 31)
The
mind is not born with the individual but develops in the context of human
interaction and the mind is not only internal but also external, mainly
external, that is, the pragmatic context of interpersonal relationships. The internal space is
something that is created, as we can see, for example, in the description supplied
by Vygotsky (1977) of how the egocentric speech is built, as an intermediate
phase or ‘transition’ between the external language (social) and inner speech,
when the child is talking to himself, for example, explaining the actions of
his game, for anyone but
himself, but aloud.
Morris
Eagle (2011, p. 170), not long ago, said that in the current psychoanalytic
literature representations are unconscious not only because they are defensive
processes but because they have been acquired nonverbally in the early stages
of life. He is referring to the procedural unconscious (Cf. Lyons-Ruth, 1999). However,
when he added, correctly, that these representations are similar to the habits
and motoric skills incorporated into the body, why continue to maintain that they
are ‘representations’? Human beings, like any organism, behaves usually following
a sequence of acts, that sequence can be represented by a scheme or script, the
script is a reconstruction we make ourselves and don’t have to be ‘represented’
in any way within the body or the brain.
As
Knoblauch (2000, p. 158) states, affects are not in the person but are
continually built as an emotional field that slides between people who are
influencing each other. What the person performs in practice are operational
schemes, learned in context, and not internal images.
What goes on within also
has meaning only in the stream of life. (Auch was im Innern vorghet hat nur im
Fluss des Lebens Bedeutung) (Wittgenstein, 1951, II, p.30).
Errors
arise from our tendency to give a value per
se to these internal images, when in fact the internal image has stability
only if contrasted with the use (Wittgenstein 1945-48, § 258, § 293, II, p.196/451). Whoever becomes blind, after some time, loses the ability to represent the
world in visual images. For Wittgenstein the essential postulate are not representational
systems, but interpersonal communication.
There
is no difficulty for me to recognize that the theory of mentalization provides
an integrative framework that could constitute the ‘common language’ Fonagy and
Allison (2014, p. 375) suggest. They propose mentalization; other experts
highlight other concepts: attachment, empathy, recognition, etc. Anyway Fonagy
and Allison are right when state that a key factor is:
… the patient’s
experience of another person having the
patients mind in mind, and that therapy (…) works by reviving the patient’s
capacity to interpret behaviour as
motivated by mental states, both in themselves and in others. (emphasis
added)
Whenever
we understand that ‘having the patients mind in mind’ is equivalent to empathy
and recognition, and that the patient’s capacity to ‘interpret behavior as
motivated by mental states’ could be substituted by ‘agency’. Then my
conclusion is that our differences could be in a great proportion merely
question of language, a confusion of tongues. But nonetheless I fear that some
of the expressions found in Fonagy’s texts may encourage in some novice
therapist to assume an authoritarian or dogmatic attitude.
Someday
we will have to spend no small time to resolve the issue of the representation,
and its central role in contemporary psychology, not only in its cognitive
versions.
Bibliography
Bateman,
A. and Fonagy, P. (2004). Psychotherapy
for Borderline Personality Disorders. Mentalization-based treatment.
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Bloom,
P. and German, T.P. (2000). Two reasons
to abandon the false belief task as a test of theory of mind. Cognition, 77, B25-B31.
Cavell,
M. (2006). Becoming a Subject. Reflections in Philosophy and Psychoanalysis. Nueva York:
Oxford University Press.
Eagle,
M.N. (2011). From Classical to
Contemporary Psychoanalysis. A Critic and Integration. Nueva York:
Routledge.
Fonagy,
P. (1991). Thinking about Thinking: Some Clinical and Theoretical
Considerations in the Treatment of a Borderline Patient. International Journal of Psychoanalysis, 72, 639-656.
Fonagy,
P. (1998 a). Moments of change in psychoanalytic theory: Discussion of a new
theory of psychic change. Infant Mental Health Journal, 19, 3, 346-353.
Fonagy,
P. (1999 a). The Process of Change and the Change of Processes: What can Change
in a ‘Good’ Analysis. Keynote Address to the Sprig Meeting of Division 39 of
the American Psychological Association, New York. En: http://mentalizacion.com.ar/images/notas/The%20process%20of%20change%20and%20the%20change%20of%20processes.htm .
Fonagy,
P. (1999 b). Pathological attachments and therapeutic action. Paper presented
to the Developmental and Psychoanalytic Discussion Group, American
Psychological Association Meeting, Washington DC, May 13, 1999. PsycheMatters
publication [On Line] Available: www.psychematters.com/papers/fonagy3htm.
Fonagy,
P. (2000). Attachment and Borderline Personality Disorder. Journal of the American Psychoanalytic Association, 48, 4,
1129-1146.
Fonagy,
P. (2001 a). The Psychoanalysis of Violence. Paper presented to the Dallas Society
for Psychoanalytic Psychotherapy March 15, 2001.
Fonagy,
P. (2008). The Mentalization-Focused Approach to Social Development. Chapter 1
of Frederic N. Busch (ed.) “Mentalization. Theoretical Considerations, Research
Findings, and Clinical Implications.”
New York: The Analytic Press.
Fonagy, P. and
Allison, E. (2014). The role of mentalizing and epistemic trust in the
therapeutic relationship. Psychotherapy,
51, 3, 372-380.
Fonagy, P., Steele,
M., Steele, H., Leigh, T., Kennedy, R., Mattoon, G. y Target, M. (1995).
Attachment, the reflective self, and borderline states: The predictive
specificity of the Adult Attachment Interview and pathological emotional
development. En S. Goldberg, R. Muir y J. Kerr (comp.) Attachment Theory:
Social, developmental, and clinical perspectives. Hillsdale, New Jersey:
Analytic Press.
Fonagy,
P. y Target, M. (1996). Playing with reality I. International Journal of
Psychoanalysis, 77, 217-33.
Foucault, M. (1988).
"Technologies of the Self. A Seminar with Michell Foucault", edited
by Luther H. Martin, Huck Gutman and Patrick H. Hutton, pp. 16-49. Univ. of Massachusets Press, 1988.
Foucault, M. (2001). L’Hermenéneutique du Sujet. Cours au Collège
de France. 1981-1982. Paris: Gallimard/Seuil.
Gerson, S. (2004). The
relational unconscious: A core element of intersubjectivity, thirdness, and
clinical process. Psychoanalytic Quarterly, LXXIII, 63-98.
Illich, I.
(1993). In the Vineyard of the Text: A
Commentary to Hugh's Didascalicon. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press. [En el Viñedo
del Texto. Etología de la lectura: un comentario al “Didascalicon” de Hugo de
San Víctor. México: Fondo de Cultura Económica, 2002.
Knoblauch, S.H. (2000). The Musical Edge of Therapeutic Dialogue.
Hillsdale, NJ: The
Analytic Press.
Kohut, H. (1984), How
Does Analysis Cure? Chicago:
University of Chicago Press. Traducción
castellana ¿Cómo Cura el Análisis?
Buenos Aires: Paidós, 1986.
Kohlberg, L. (1964). The development of moral character.
En M.CC. Hoffmann (comp.) Child Development. Nueva York: SAGE.
Kohlberg, L.; Levine,
C. y Hewer, A. (1984). Moral stages: a current formulation and a response to
critics. Basilea: Karger.
Lyons-Ruth, K. (1999).
The Two-Person
Unconscious: Intersubjective Dialogue, Enactive Relational Representation, and
the Emergence of New Forms of Relational Organization. Psychoanalytic Inquiry, 19, 576-617
Malcolm, N. (1986). Nothing is Hidden: Wittgenstein's Criticism
of his Early Thought. Oxford: Blackwell.
Meltzoff,
A. N. (2007). The ‘like me’ framework for recognizing and becoming an
intentional agent. Acta Psychologica, 124, 26–43.
Meltzoff,
A.N. and Moore, M.K. (1977). Imitation of Facial and Manual Gestures by Human
Neonates. Science, 198, 75-78.
Orange, D. M., Atwood,
G. E., Stolorow, R. D. (1997). Working Intersubjectively. Contextualism in
Psychoanalytic Practice. Hillsdale: The Analytic Press.
Ryle, G. (1949). The Concept of Mind. Nueva York: Barnes
& Noble.
Snell, B. (2007). El
Descubrimiento del Espíritu. Estudios sobre la génesis del pensamiento europeo
en los griegos. Barcelona: Acantilado.
Sperry, M. (2013).
Putting our heads together: Mentalizing systems. Psychoanalytic Dialogues, 23, 6, 683-699.
Stolorow, R.D.,
Orange, D.M., y Atwood, G.E. (2001).
Cartesian and post-Cartesian trends in relational psychoanalysis. Psychoanalytic
Psychology, 18, 468-484.
Target, M. y Fonagy,
P. (1996). Playing with reality: 2. The development of psychic reality from a
theoretical perspective. International Journal of Psycho-Analysis, 77, 459-479.
Wellman, H. M., &
Liu, D. (2004). Scaling of theory of mind tasks. Child Development, 75, 2, 523-541.
Wittgenstein, L.
(1945-48). Zettel (Z). Traducción
inglesa de G.E.M. Anscombe; Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1981.
Wittgenstein, L. (1945‑49).
Philosophical Investigations. Traducción inglesa de G.E.M. Anscombe;
Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1984. Revised 4th edition by P.M.S. Hacker and Joachim Schulte. Oxford:
Wiley-Blackwell, 2009: The German text, with an English translation. Edición bilingüe alemán‑español de Alfonso García Suárez y
Ulises Moulines "Investigaciones Filosóficas"; Barcelona:
Crítica, 1988.
Wittgenstein, L.
(1951). Last Writings on the Philosophy of Psychology . Volúmenes I (1948-1949) y II (1949-1951). Ediciones bilingües
alemán inglés, traducciones de C.G. Luckardt y M.A.E. Aue, G.H. von Wright y H.
Nyman (eds.). Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
Vygotsky, L.S. (1977). Pensamiento y Lenguaje. Buenos Aires: La
Pléyade.
Vygotsky, L.S. (1989).
Concrete Human
Psychology. Soviet Psychology, 27, 53-77.
No hay comentarios:
Publicar un comentario